Monday 9 June 2014

LIBERTY OF TRUTH AND DISCUSSIONS - JOHN STUART MILL

 John Stuart Mill devoted most of his famous account to explaining why freedom of discussion is important.  The general idea is that truth is a casualty of the suppression of free discussion. Pressing more is when this freedom may be limited, though freedom of discussion was widely accepted even in Mill’s own day, he thinks that the arguments for it are not widely appreciated.

Mill as an utilitarian rejects the idea of natural rights, and emphasizes that society as a whole, not just the silenced individual, loses by the state of possible subjugation of free discussion.

 In effect there are three arguments that are attached to three possible scenarios.

In the first, argument, he imagines that a majority who share a certain view seek to silence the minority who disagree. He further supposes that the majority view is false, as it happens, it makes the minority view true. Mill argues that in these circumstances it is catastrophic to silence the minority, disastrous for the majority, that is, because there is now no means of releasing it from its belief in a fallacious reasoning. If however the minority remains free to express its doubts about the majority view, then there is a chance that the majority will be brought to see the falsity of its view.

The second scenario is the same as the first except that this time the majority view is true and the minority view false. Here a concern for truth might seem to support silencing the minority since its view is false. Bottling fallacy doubtlessly supports truth. However, he argues that if the majority silences its opponents, it will never have to defend its belief and over time will forget the arguments for it.

Mill’s third scenario involves both parties of opinion, majority and minority, having a portion of the truth but not the whole of it. He regards this as the most common of the three scenarios, and his argument here is very simple. To enlarge its grasp of the truth the majority must allow the minority to express its halfway truthful view.

On assessment of the case, the first and third of Mill’s arguments are the most persuasive. If the majority view is wholly or partially false, then allowing critical discussion surely enhances the chances of truth replacing error. But if the majority view is already true, as in the second argument, allowing critical discussion does involve risk.

Majorities, he says will always think that they are in the second scenario, where the case for allowing critical discussion is weakest. They, like anyone else, will always take their beliefs to be true. Thinking a belief true is a condition of having it. Mill supposes, that we can never be certain that our beliefs are true, his position is that we can never have the degree of certainty that would warrant silencing criticism of our beliefs. That would be to claim infallibility for ourselves. If however we allow our beliefs to be criticized but no persuasive criticism is forthcoming, that gives us sufficient certainty to warrant our acting upon the beliefs.

 When we come to the political, moral and religious cases where that temptation is real, then it is much more plausible to think, with Mill, that we cannot have certainty of the sort required to justify the abbreviation of debate. For in these cases there are always contemplation on both sides of the argument which have to be balanced.

2 comments: